Discussion about this post

User's avatar
Lloyd Garnett's avatar

Excellent article. Thank you.

One point tho arguably not central to your essay, is important.

The main point of the Declaration of Independence is that free people have a right to be governed by their consent … even if it requires dissolving the political bonds of an existing, injurious government to form another, more supportive of their Rights and interests … BECAUSE their CREATOR has gifted them “the Rights to life, liberty and the pursuit of happiness”. In other words, those three Rights are justification for self government (and by inference, the price of attaining it).

My 2 cts (adjusted for actual currency devaluation and not, sadly, the Bureau of Labor Statistics’ deceitful claim)

Expand full comment
Alec Rawls's avatar

Thanks for this essay. I hadn't heard before of Madison's idea that just laws should respond in some degree to an outcomes-based concept of equity. Something like this was eventually formalized by the late moral philosopher John Rawls (my father), who proposed that a just society must be responsive to claims of need.

As he originally stated his project in his early "Justice as Fairness" essay, Rawls sought to find "a proper balance" between three types of competing claims: claims of "liberty, equality, and reward for services contributing to the common good."

One way to find this "proper balance," he suggested, would be to set up a rule-making process that made it impossible for the rule-makers to arrange the rules to favor their own particular circumstances. Such rules would then be "fair" in the sense that they would not be tilted in anyone's favor, and if the rules were rules of justice, these fair rules would be legitimate, or valid, rules of justice.

Thus in Justice as Fairness rule-makers were tasked to come up with just rules for a repeated game, where they would randomly find themselves in a different position each time the game was played. If they tried to favor their current position, they would find themselves on the dis-favored side in subsequent go-rounds.

In this game, liberty and reward for contribution are the Hamiltonian part of the justice equation. Reward for contribution comes primarily in the form of market wages and profits, which operate through liberty of contract.

Equality is the Madisonian part of justice, referring not just to equal rights (which are actually part of liberty), but also to inequality of outcomes, and whether there is a point at which such inequalities become intolerable, or unjust.

This "equality" part of the equation is what Rawls ended up describing, in his later Theory of Justice (1971), in terms of a need to answer claims of need, which seems right. We can't be concerned just about differences in relative welfare, because that becomes envy, which Rawls described as an "antisocial sentiment" that cannot be part of any genuine concept of justice.

What matters is a person's absolute level of welfare, and this is easily seen via the repeated game scheme for locating fair rules. Rule-makers for a repeated game where no one knows what position he will occupy next, will all very much want for as few people as possible to fall into stunting conditions, where they never have a chance to attain much of their potential, affirming the need to answer claims of need.

That brings up the next question: is there a way for society to insure that such needs are met without destroying liberty and reward for contribution? Trying to figure that out was a great project, but Rawls failed in the execution.

He got bollixed up when he tried to refine his scheme for setting up a rulemaking context in which rule-makers could not write the rules to their own advantage.

He decided to switch from a repeated game to a position of choice behind a "veil of ignorance" about one's place in society. That's fine, but the problem is how he tried to justify this new formulation.

It didn't actually need any new justification. Since the veil of ignorance scheme would keep rule-makers from being able to tilt rules in their own favor, the rules arrived at in this hypothetical situation would be fair, just as in his original "Justice as Fairness" scheme.

Nevertheless, Rawls did try to supply an additional form of justification, and it messed everything up.

He decided to characterize the information about a person's particular circumstances that was being hidden as information that was morally irrelevant: the reason it was being excluded from deliberations about principles of justice is because it was irrelevant to those deliberations.

Sounds compelling. Leave out what is morally extraneous and the result will be pure justice. The problem is that this required finding some way to classify absolutely every aspect of everyone's actual position in the world to be morally irrelevant, or else people would be allowed to know that part about their actual circumstances, and would be able to use that information to tip rules in their own favor.

In particular, because desert is a moral concept, ways had to be found to deny that anyone can ever be said to deserve any of what they have, or that possession would be morally relevant.

Thus for Rawls' veil of ignorance to even exist, all claims of desert had to be denied from the outset. But that meant denying that anyone ever has any legitimate claims of due based on reward for having made a contribution.

By trying to arrive at his veil of ignorance by getting rid of morally irrelevant information, Rawls was forced to eliminate from his analysis the second most important category of claims that he had originally set out to balance against other claims.

Only claims of liberty (most important) and claims of need remained, with no weight given to however much a person might have contributed to society. It was a complete capsizing of Rawls' own original project, which had shown so much promise.

I have known for many years that I had a family obligation to one day fix this momentous mistake, not just because my father's Theory of Justice ended up asserting some very wrong and destructive equalitarian conclusions, but because a great chance to seek for reconciliation between claims of desert and claims of need (Hamiltonian and Madisonian values, I can now call them), had been missed.

In 2021 I finally got the chance to try to reverse these losses when my friend Bill Evers told the editors of The Independent Review that I might be able to write something for their upcoming retrospective on the 50th anniversary of Rawls's book.

They let me write a substantial piece, explaining where Theory went wrong and how to get it right, at which point a powerful reconciliation between claims of desert and claims of need is seen to be possible.

If anyone is interested, just search <Theory of Justice with claims of desert,  Independent Review>.

Regards, Alec Rawls

Expand full comment
19 more comments...

No posts